![]() |
Metamath Proof Explorer |
< Previous
Next >
Nearby theorems |
Mirrors > Home > MPE Home > Th. List > axsep | Unicode version |
Description: Separation Scheme, which
is an axiom scheme of Zermelo's original
theory. Scheme Sep of [BellMachover] p. 463. As we show here, it
is
redundant if we assume Replacement in the form of ax-rep 4563. Some
textbooks present Separation as a separate axiom scheme in order to show
that much of set theory can be derived without the stronger
Replacement. The Separation Scheme is a weak form of Frege's Axiom of
Comprehension, conditioning it (with ) so that it asserts the
existence of a collection only if it is smaller than some other
collection that already exists. This
prevents Russell's paradox
ru 3326. In some texts, this scheme is called
"Aussonderung" or the
Subset Axiom.
The variable can appear free in the wff
, which in
textbooks is often written For a version using a class variable, see zfauscl 4575, which requires the Axiom of Extensionality as well as Separation for its derivation. If we omit the requirement that not occur in , we can derive a contradiction, as notzfaus 4627 shows (contradicting zfauscl 4575). However, as axsep2 4574 shows, we can eliminate the restriction that not occur in . Note: the distinct variable restriction that not occur in is actually redundant in this particular proof, but we keep it since its purpose is to demonstrate the derivation of the exact ax-sep 4573 from ax-rep 4563. This theorem should not be referenced by any proof. Instead, use ax-sep 4573 below so that the uses of the Axiom of Separation can be more easily identified. (Contributed by NM, 11-Sep-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Ref | Expression |
---|---|
axsep |
Step | Hyp | Ref | Expression |
---|---|---|---|
1 | nfv 1707 | . . . 4 | |
2 | 1 | axrep5 4568 | . . 3 |
3 | equtr 1796 | . . . . . . . 8 | |
4 | equcomi 1793 | . . . . . . . 8 | |
5 | 3, 4 | syl6 33 | . . . . . . 7 |
6 | 5 | adantrd 468 | . . . . . 6 |
7 | 6 | alrimiv 1719 | . . . . 5 |
8 | 7 | a1d 25 | . . . 4 |
9 | 8 | spimev 2010 | . . 3 |
10 | 2, 9 | mpg 1620 | . 2 |
11 | an12 797 | . . . . . . 7 | |
12 | 11 | exbii 1667 | . . . . . 6 |
13 | nfv 1707 | . . . . . . 7 | |
14 | elequ1 1821 | . . . . . . . 8 | |
15 | 14 | anbi1d 704 | . . . . . . 7 |
16 | 13, 15 | equsex 2038 | . . . . . 6 |
17 | 12, 16 | bitr3i 251 | . . . . 5 |
18 | 17 | bibi2i 313 | . . . 4 |
19 | 18 | albii 1640 | . . 3 |
20 | 19 | exbii 1667 | . 2 |
21 | 10, 20 | mpbi 208 | 1 |
Colors of variables: wff setvar class |
Syntax hints: -> wi 4 <-> wb 184
/\ wa 369 A. wal 1393 E. wex 1612 |
This theorem was proved from axioms: ax-mp 5 ax-1 6 ax-2 7 ax-3 8 ax-gen 1618 ax-4 1631 ax-5 1704 ax-6 1747 ax-7 1790 ax-8 1820 ax-9 1822 ax-10 1837 ax-11 1842 ax-12 1854 ax-13 1999 ax-rep 4563 |
This theorem depends on definitions: df-bi 185 df-an 371 df-tru 1398 df-ex 1613 df-nf 1617 |
Copyright terms: Public domain | W3C validator |